友情提示:如果本网页打开太慢或显示不完整,请尝试鼠标右键“刷新”本网页!阅读过程发现任何错误请告诉我们,谢谢!! 报告错误
热门书库 返回本书目录 我的书架 我的书签 TXT全本下载 进入书吧 加入书签

prior analytics-第14章

按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!






first figure; and the conclusion that A may possibly belong to some of



the Bs。 For when one of the premisses in the first figure is



problematic; the conclusion also (as we saw) is problematic。 Similarly



if the proposition BC is pure; AC problematic; or if AC is negative;



BC affirmative; no matter which of the two is pure; in both cases



the conclusion will be problematic: for the first figure is obtained



once more; and it has been proved that if one premiss is problematic



in that figure the conclusion also will be problematic。 But if the



minor premiss BC is negative; or if both premisses are negative; no



syllogistic conclusion can be drawn from the premisses as they



stand; but if they are converted a syllogism is obtained as before。



  If one of the premisses is universal; the other particular; then



when both are affirmative; or when the universal is negative; the



particular affirmative; we shall have the same sort of syllogisms: for



all are completed by means of the first figure。 So it is clear that we



shall have not a pure but a problematic syllogistic conclusion。 But if



the affirmative premiss is universal; the negative particular; the



proof will proceed by a reductio ad impossibile。 Suppose that B



belongs to all C; and A may possibly not belong to some C: it



follows that may possibly not belong to some B。 For if A necessarily



belongs to all B; and B (as has been assumed) belongs to all C; A will



necessarily belong to all C: for this has been proved before。 But it



was assumed at the outset that A may possibly not belong to some C。



  Whenever both premisses are indefinite or particular; no syllogism



will be possible。 The demonstration is the same as was given in the



case of universal premisses; and proceeds by means of the same terms。







                                22







  If one of the premisses is necessary; the other problematic; when



the premisses are affirmative a problematic affirmative conclusion can



always be drawn; when one proposition is affirmative; the other



negative; if the affirmative is necessary a problematic negative can



be inferred; but if the negative proposition is necessary both a



problematic and a pure negative conclusion are possible。 But a



necessary negative conclusion will not be possible; any more than in



the other figures。 Suppose first that the premisses are affirmative;



i。e。 that A necessarily belongs to all C; and B may possibly belong to



all C。 Since then A must belong to all C; and C may belong to some



B; it follows that A may (not does) belong to some B: for so it



resulted in the first figure。 A similar proof may be given if the



proposition BC is necessary; and AC is problematic。 Again suppose



one proposition is affirmative; the other negative; the affirmative



being necessary: i。e。 suppose A may possibly belong to no C; but B



necessarily belongs to all C。 We shall have the first figure once



more: and…since the negative premiss is problematic…it is clear that



the conclusion will be problematic: for when the premisses stand



thus in the first figure; the conclusion (as we found) is problematic。



But if the negative premiss is necessary; the conclusion will be not



only that A may possibly not belong to some B but also that it does



not belong to some B。 For suppose that A necessarily does not belong



to C; but B may belong to all C。 If the affirmative proposition BC



is converted; we shall have the first figure; and the negative premiss



is necessary。 But when the premisses stood thus; it resulted that A



might possibly not belong to some C; and that it did not belong to



some C; consequently here it follows that A does not belong to some B。



But when the minor premiss is negative; if it is problematic we



shall have a syllogism by altering the premiss into its



complementary affirmative; as before; but if it is necessary no



syllogism can be formed。 For A sometimes necessarily belongs to all B;



and sometimes cannot possibly belong to any B。 To illustrate the



former take the terms sleep…sleeping horse…man; to illustrate the



latter take the terms sleep…waking horse…man。



  Similar results will obtain if one of the terms is related



universally to the middle; the other in part。 If both premisses are



affirmative; the conclusion will be problematic; not pure; and also



when one premiss is negative; the other affirmative; the latter



being necessary。 But when the negative premiss is necessary; the



conclusion also will be a pure negative proposition; for the same kind



of proof can be given whether the terms are universal or not。 For



the syllogisms must be made perfect by means of the first figure; so



that a result which follows in the first figure follows also in the



third。 But when the minor premiss is negative and universal; if it



is problematic a syllogism can be formed by means of conversion; but



if it is necessary a syllogism is not possible。 The proof will



follow the same course as where the premisses are universal; and the



same terms may be used。



  It is clear then in this figure also when and how a syllogism can be



formed; and when the conclusion is problematic; and when it is pure。



It is evident also that all syllogisms in this figure are imperfect;



and that they are made perfect by means of the first figure。







                                23







  It is clear from what has been said that the syllogisms in these



figures are made perfect by means of universal syllogisms in the first



figure and are reduced to them。 That every syllogism without



qualification can be so treated; will be clear presently; when it



has been proved that every syllogism is formed through one or other of



these figures。



  It is necessary that every demonstration and every syllogism



should prove either that something belongs or that it does not; and



this either universally or in part; and further either ostensively



or hypothetically。 One sort of hypothetical proof is the reductio ad



impossibile。 Let us speak first of ostensive syllogisms: for after



these have been pointed out the truth of our contention will be



clear with regard to those which are proved per impossibile; and in



general hypothetically。



  If then one wants to prove syllogistically A of B; either as an



attribute of it or as not an attribute of it; one must assert



something of something else。 If now A should be asserted of B; the



proposition originally in question will have been assumed。 But if A



should be asserted of C; but C should not be asserted of anything; nor



anything of it; nor anything else of A; no syllogism will be possible。



For nothing necessarily fol
返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 0 0
未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
温馨提示: 温看小说的同时发表评论,说出自己的看法和其它小伙伴们分享也不错哦!发表书评还可以获得积分和经验奖励,认真写原创书评 被采纳为精评可以获得大量金币、积分和经验奖励哦!